Parameters of
Perception: Vision, Audition, and Twentieth-Century Music and Dance
Congress on Research
in Dance 38th Annual Conference
November 2-5, 2006,
Tempe, Arizona
Recent
experimental psychological research on visual perception, auditory perception,
and cross-modal perception has shed light on how these processes differ, and
how the relations between visual and auditory stimuli shade our understanding
of the events perceived. This work
offers a possible way into considering the question of how music and dance go
together or not, and particularly may shed light on the unusual
twentieth-century human behavior of NOT having music and dance go
together. Our paper presents
relevant research in perception, examines factors contributing to the
separation of perceptual modalities that has often appeared in
twentieth-century dance, and discusses the separation in terms of the specific
behaviors of dancing and looking at dance.
We
come to this paper with a practical interest in what makes music and dance go
together, or not, in that one of us choreographs and one of us composes and we
share a desire to make computer-interactive pieces. In such pieces the connection between movement and sound
must be examined explicitly, and this has led us to explore the literature from
experimental psychology relating sound to movement and attempt to connect it to
the making and viewing of dances.
We
start by trying to distinguish between cases where dance and music are seen to
go together and those where they arent. The latter appear to be unusual in human history. Indeed one standard explanation for the
evolution of music and dance hypothesizes that they contribute to group
cohesion (McNeill 1995, Cross 1999, Brown 2001, Hagen and Bryant 2003), and
perhaps the traditional cohesion of music and dance not only reflects but is
constitutive of that function.[1] Many languages do not distinguish
between dance and music but have one word denoting both together (Besson and
Schn 2001).[2] All peoples have some dance with music,
and usually dance and music occur in tandem and intertwine (Hanna 1982, 60-61;
Brown 1991, 140).[3]
But
what is it about dance and music that makes them go together? Or more precisely, from the observers
standpoint, in what ways does a dance and its accompaniment seem to fit each
other? In this paper we consider
three sound-motion phenomena that contribute to answers to these questions.[4] First we look briefly at simple
congruence, where similarities or alignments are perceived between the two
media (Krumhansl and Schenck 1997, Mitchell and Gallaher 2001). Then we turn to various types of
capture, where similarities and alignments are not seen until the media are
presented together (Repp and Penel 2002; Sekuler, Sekuler and Lau 1997;
Watanabe and Shimojo 2005). And
finally we consider virtual motion, the movement which is felt or imagined when
sound is heard.[5]
Most
immediately relevant to music and dance is the idea of congruence. In a 1997 study, Carol Krumhansl and
Diana Schenck used Balanchines choreography set to Mozarts Divertimento No.
15 to specifically address whether dance could reflect the structural and
expressive qualities of music. Their participants were asked to 1) watch the
choreography in silence, 2) listen to the music without seeing the dance, or 3)
watch the dance and listen to the music together. All three groups were then
asked to rate the tension and emotion throughout the piece as well as indicate
the beginnings and endings of phrases. Results showed that all three groups
concurred in their judgments and that the response to the both music and
dance condition could be predicted as a combination of the responses to the
music only and dance only conditions.
Krumhansl and Schenck, following the ideas of Paul Hodgins (1992,
25-30), who proposed a detailed paradigm for choreomusical analysis, attribute
the parallel responses to parallel elements in the dance and music, including
structural organizations, rhythms, dynamics, qualities of motion, and tempi.[6]
Robert
Mitchell and Matthew Gallahers 2001 study examined the ability to detect a
match between a piece of music and choreography intended to go with it. The musical pieces were by John Cage,
Peter Gabriel, and David Lanz, and the dances were by Mitchell and Gallahers
colleague Marianne McAdams.[7] Participants were presented with a
piece of choreography in silence followed by three selections of music. They
were then asked to choose the musical selection that best matched the choreography.
Participants were also presented with a piece of choreography paired with a
piece of music, either intended or not intended to go with it. In both the
sequential and simultaneous test format Mitchell and Gallahers results show
consistently high ratings for perceiving a match between a piece of music and
choreography intended to go with it.
Participants answers to a questionnaire indicated that their matches
were influenced by similar characteristics perceived in the media, including
emotion, fluidity, an African or Middle Eastern quality, and temporal
characteristics such as rhythm and pace.
Again, congruence was found to be a result of similarities perceived in
the movement and the sound.
Combining
a categorical scheme of Mitchell and Gallaher with the analytical framework of
Hodgins yields a short list[8]
of parallels between music and dance that may contribute to a sense of
congruency:
(1)
matching or intertwining pulse[9]
or rhythm.
(2)
alignment of structural temporal aspects
other than pulse that coincide.
(3)
analogous cross-modal qualities.
(4)
complementary referents.[10]
These results are certainly quite
intuitive and predictable, but we are equally interested in examining instances
where music and dance are NOT intended to go together. We earlier noted a human tendency
towards cohesion in dance and music, yet there has been considerable
experimentation in the 20th-century in producing works in which sound and
movement seem to be more complementary or even in competition rather than congruent. We would like to briefly consider how
that came about before turning to the phenomenon of auditory and visual
capture.
Claims
that music was being used as only a sonic backdrop, not as rhythmic material to
which dancers coordinated their steps, can be traced at least back to some of
the works of the Ballets Russes and the Parisian avant-garde.[11] In Nijinskys LAprs-midi dun
faune (1912) the score is reduced to
background music (Buckle 1971, 164).[12] In Cocteaus Le Boeuf sur le
Toit (1920), the characters perform in
slow motion, against the music (1955, 16).[13] Similarly silent film could be
presented with music that seemed unconnected.[14] As described by Wilfred Mellers (1942,
224), Saties minimalist music for the intermission film in Relche (1924) provides a background: it nowhere tries to
give musical expression to the images of the screen.[15]
It
is in film where a developed theorization of the asynchrony of sound and image
first appears in the late 1920s.[16] But in films like Battleship Potemkin (1925) by the best known of film theorists, the
Russian Sergei Eisenstein, music and visuals are still closely related,
although perhaps in complex ways.[17] In contrast, the theory of the independence of music and movement that has been present in American modern dance since
the 1950s, traceable to John Cage and Merce Cunningham, rejects imposing a
unity. Cage and Cunninghams ideas
can be seen as descending from the practical and theoretical concerns of the
composer Henry Cowell, who through the 1930s was developing an elastic form of
accompaniment in response to American modern dance choreographers chafing at
dance being slave to music.[18] The process of de-linking dance from
music was finally brought to its logical endpoint with Cage composing indeterminate
scores that shared only a common duration with the dance, so that dancers, as
Cunningham relates, could not count on the sounds as cues, and had to rely
on [their] own dance timing to guard the length of any phrase (1992, 142-143).[19] The Cage/Cunningham approach to dance
and music has had continuing influence, directly affecting the choreographers
in the Judson Dance Theater and even distantly marking multimedia performance
such as that directed by Robert Wilson.[20]
This
path to cross-modal incongruence has been influenced by many cultural and
historical factors peculiar to western Europe and the United States that might
encourage a conceptualization of music and dance as parallel lines of
objectively experienced materials.
There is the ideology of autonomous listening and viewing associated
with the concert hall tradition.
In tandem with this is the structural and syntactic emphasis in
attending to concert music most ably described and theorized by Leonard Meyer
(1956; 1994), which encourages discerning contrapuntal activity and
hierarchical simultaneities. Audio
recordings and silent films allowed the experiencing of sound and movement as
separate events. Finally we note
that Cages (1961, 109-145) explanatory framework borrowed from Zen Buddhism an
acceptance of simultaneity—in particular that of any sound with any
movement.[21]
But
in practice multimodal incongruence seems difficult to achieve. While sound and movement may be
produced independently in a Cunningham dance, their reception is hard to keep
separate. In our experience of
watching his work, not only does each medium have hooks that grab elements
of the other medium to create coincidental events, but qualities of the music
and the dance often seem complementary, something occasionally also true of
their referential meanings. Each
instance of coincident sound and movement is perhaps experienced as a
perceptual unity akin to the McGurk Effect, a classic form of what is called
capture, to which we now turn.
The
McGurk Effect (McGurk and MacDonald 1976) is what happens when a visual image
of a person saying ba is paired with an auditory track of someone saying
ga, resulting in a composite perception of seeing and hearing a person say
da. The significance of the
McGurk Effect is that it shows how simultaneous presentation of auditory and
visual stimuli capitalizes on a model of optimal combination. The combination is optimal because it
combines the information from each medium into a composite interpretation that
makes the most sense.
This
optimal combination model may extend beyond speech into more abstract
representations, as may be seen in the bounce-inducing effect, which can be
produced as follows. Viewers are
shown two identical discs moving toward each other in a straight line. They meet and then move apart,
continuing along the line.
Normally they are seen to pass through each other. But if a sound is heard at the time the
discs meet, they are instead seen to bounce off each other and return in the
direction from which they came.
While the bounce-inducing effect can be interpreted as an instance of
optimal combination, it is undoubtedly one in which audition dominates. This is called auditory capture, for
the visual stimulus is perceived differently when combined with the auditory
stimulus—the auditory stimulus captures the visual. Likewise there may be visual capture
of auditory stimuli.
Extending
the idea of capture to the more complex stimuli that interest us, Scott
Lipscomb and Roger Kendall (1994) paired an abstract film excerpt with a
variety of different musical accompaniments and found that viewers perceived
several musical choices as a good fit.
Similarly the study by Mitchell and Gallaher (2001) mentioned earlier
showed not only that dances intended to match their music were indeed seen to
do so, but also that there was a significant perception of matching between
dances and music not intended to go together.[22] This is to be expected, for whether or
not relationships between music and dance are intended by their creators,
viewers will inevitably attempt to construct connections between experiences
that are coincident in time according to the Gestalt principles of perception
(Sloboda 1985). It has been shown
that even when the intention of congruence between the auditory and the visual
is removed, congruence can still be perceived and in fact very likely will be perceived (Bolivar, Cohen and Fentress 1994;
Iwamiya 1994; Lipscomb and Kendall 1994).[23] As Mitchell and Gallaher conclude,
simultaneous presentation of visual and auditory stimuli (e.g., dance and
music) may enhance the experience of a match between them from only a few
similarities (67). This is
because viewers actively look for cross-modal perceptual congruences formed by
capture.
While
capture can help explain how some music and dance judged incongruent separately
may seem congruent when judged together, there still are combinations of dance
and music in which the media remain stubbornly incongruent no matter what. For these cases perhaps a process
somewhat opposite to capture may kick in.
Roger Copeland argues that the independence of music and dance in
Cunninghams work contributes to a championing of perceptual freedom,[24]
where multimodal incongruence helps disable our tendency to fuse simultaneous
events and helps make us aware of the individual characteristics of sounds and
movements, spurring us to attempt to follow them with selective or divided
attention so far as we are able.[25] The sort of skills this requires are
cultivated for example by listening to polyphonic music, for which the ability
to hear multiple lines of music simultaneously pays dividends.[26],[27] The analogous problem for dance would
be following multiple dancers or multiple groups of dancers.[28]
It
is not clear how easily humans may follow independent musical and dancing
objects simultaneously, but certainly a byproduct of the attempt to see the
parts instead of the whole is to notice details—of individual dancers, of
their group dynamics, and of their relationship to the music—without them
joining into a unitary experience.
The writer Italo Calvino speaks of the contemporary novel as a network
of connections between the events, the people, and the things of the world, a
multiplication of possibilities (1988, 105 and 124), and such description may
perhaps be applied to dance that moves without regard for its music. When the relationships between
modalities become indirect and complex, the dance will seem most familiar to an
audience entrained by the multiplicities of our urban, global, networked,
multi-tasking world.
But
this audience of multi-tasking viewers experiences the dance differently from
the dancers. While musicians and
their listeners hear approximately the same mix of sound, dancers and their viewers
do not see the same field of movement:
the dancers are within a changing array while the observer is
without. Yet dancing and looking
at dance cannot be entirely separate experiences. Ivar Hagendoorn (2004) has recently proposed that the
experience of watching dance creates pleasure for us through the fulfilling and
undermining of our expectations.
The prediction mechanism that drives the expectations is our kinesthetic
response to movement[29]—an
embodied response gaining experimental credence due to accumulating evidence
that the brain pathways for action and perception are the same. While the dancer dances on stage, the
viewers to some extent sense the dancers movement as if they were doing it
themselves.
Hagendoorns
proposal of a neurobiological system for a kinesthetic response to dance aligns
with the musicologist Charles Keils notion of engendered feeling. Keil associates engendered feeling
especially with the motor drive prominent in many Western and non-Western
popular musics—the groove or swing which is linked strongly to dance
(1966).[30] While Keils groove is felt as
repetitive movement in music (and dance), and Hagendoorns kinesthetic response
is felt as actions by the body of the dancer (in the body of the spectator),
they are linked by the perception of feeling movement. Music psychologist Eric Clarke (2005,
62-90) argues further that human beings have a tendency to hear movement not
just in groove music but in all music,
movement which may be felt as self-motion or, especially in highly polyphonic
music, as the multiple motions of external agents.[31] Given all the felt movement induced by
hearing music and watching dance, perhaps the congruence or incongruence of
music and dance is sensed by the audience as the congruence or incongruence of
the virtual motion of the music and the virtual motion of their kinesthetic
response to the dancing.
The
virtual motion evoked by music, however, has been found to be asymmetrical,
sometimes counterintuitive, and sometimes untrue to the physical properties of
sound in the real world. In a recent study Zohar Eitan and Roni Granot (2006)
asked people to visualize the movement of an animated human character in
response to various musical selections. Participants responses clearly show that
the fact that a musical stimulus seems to suggest a particular kinetic quality
does not imply that an opposing musical stimulus suggests the opposite kinetic
quality. For many people, for example, when pitch ascended their characters
moved faster, but when pitch descended their characters did not move slower;
however, when pitch descended, their characters moved to the left, but when it
ascended, the characters did not move right. Thus the overall picture emerging from this study shows that
the perceptual relationship between sound and motion can be far more nuanced
than entrenched analogies and direct one to one mappings suggest.
One
other interesting characteristic of musics virtual motion is that it may be
still. Clarke, in arguing that all
music implies motion, includes the limiting possibility that the motion
specified by sound could be none—that is, there may be stasis.[32] His example (210 n. 7) is LaMonte
Youngs Composition 1960 no. 7, which
consists of a perfect fifth on two strings played, as directed by the composer,
for a very long time. Much of
the music of Cage, his colleagues, and other collaborators of Cunningham, falls
close to this example, allowing us to propose that what Cage and Cunningham
discovered was not so much the independence of music and dance, but rather the
complete congruence of the real motion of dance with the virtual stillness of
random sounds. Cage created music
as environment for dance, not as partner in movement. This would imply that, for dances set to Cageian soundscapes,
the audience is NOT following independent musical and dancing objects
simultaneously, but following a dancing figure or figures against a sonic
ground.
While
such music implies stillness, it still requires movement for its
production—at least it did until the twentieth century. Music requires the movement of
musicians, but the invention of sound recording broke that intimate
connection. Recorded sound limits
the interaction of music and dance, for while dancers may still respond to
music, without musicians the music cannot respond to dance. With the introduction of computer-based
interactivity between dancers and music, the connection between movement and
sound must once again be made immediate, and furthermore it must now be made
explicit, for what might have been intuitive or the result of long experience
must now be programmed. What we
hope to have shown by examining congruency, capture, and virtual motion is that
the relationship between sound and movement is both a close one and a complex
one. The connections are not
direct; the mapping is not one-to-one.
In fact, the way in which an interactive system maps sound onto movement
can actually change a viewers perception of that movement or focus their
attention to a particular quality of that movement. These findings, while relevant to us for their application
to computer-interactive dance, are equally of use in the analysis of more
traditional dance, where dancers and musicians together create moving
performances, capturing the attention of their audiences both artistically and
perceptually.
Bibliography
Altman, Rick.
Introduction. Yale French Studies 60
(1980, Cinema/Sound): 3-15.
Arnheim,
Rudolf. Film As Art. Berkeley: U of
California P, 1957.
Arom, Simha. African
Polyphony and Polyrhythm: Musical Structure and Methodology. Cambridge: Cambridge U P, 1991.
---. Liner
notes to the LP Central African Republic: Banda Polyphony. Philips, 1976. Rpt. as CD. Auvidis-UNESCO, 1999.
---. Prolegomena
to a biomusicology. Ch. 2 in The Origins of Music. Ed. Nils L. Wallin, Bjrn Merker and Steven Brown.
Cambridge: MIT P, 2000. 27-29.
Balkwill,
Laura-Lee and William Forde Thompson. A Cross-Cultural Investigation of the
Perception of Emotion in Music: Psychophysical and Cultural Cues. Music
Perception 17.1 (1999): 43-64.
Balkwill,
Laure-Lee, William Forde Thompson and Rie Matsunaga. Recognition of Emotion in
Japanese, Western, and Hindustani Music by Japanese Listeners. Japanese
Psychological Research 46.4 (2004):
337-349.
Banes, Sally.
Dancing [with/to/before/on/in/over/after/against/away from/without] the Music:
Vicissitudes of Collaboration in American Postmodern Choreography. Choreography
and Dance 1.4 (1992): 3-22. Rpt. in Writing
Dancing in the Age of Postmodernism.
Hanover: Wesleyan U P, 1994. 310-326.
---. Democracys
Body: Judson Dance Theater, 1962-1964. Ann
Arbor: UMI Research P, 1983.
Batson, Charles
R. Dance, Desire, and Anxiety in Early Twentieth-Century French Theater:
Playing Identities. Burlington: Ashgate,
2005.
Besson, Mireille
and Daniele Schn. Comparison between Language and Music. Annals of the
New York Academy of Sciences 930 (2001):
232-258.
Bigand,
Emmanuel, Stephen McAdams and S. Fort. Divided Attention in Music. International
Journal of Psychology 35.6 (2000): 270-278.
Blacking, John.
The Concept of Identity and Folk Concepts of Self: A Venda Case Study. Identity:
Personal and Socio-Cultural. Ed. Anita
Jacobson-Widding. Stockholm: Almqvist and Wiksell, 1983. 47-65.
Bolivar,
Valerie J., Annabel J. Cohen and John C. Fentress. Semantic and Formal
Congruency in Music and Motion Pictures: Effects on the Interpretation of
Visual Action. Psychomusicology 13
(1994): 28-59.
Bregman, Albert
S. Auditory Scene Analysis: The Perceptual Organization of Sound. Cambridge: MIT P, 1990.
Brown, Donald
E. Human Universals. New York:
McGraw-Hill, 1991.
Brown, Steven.
Evolutionary Models of Music: From Sexual Selection to Group Selection. Perspectives
in Ethology 13 (2001): 231-281.
Buckle,
Richard. Nijinsky. New York: Simon and
Schuster, 1971.
Cage, John. Silence. Middletown: Wesleyan U P, 1961.
Calvino, Italo.
Six Memos for the Next Millennium.
Cambridge: Harvard U P, 1988.
Chion, Michel. Audio-Vision:
Sound on Screen. Ed. and trans. Claudia
Gorbman. New York: Columbia U P, 1994.
Clair, Ren. Cinema,
Yesterday and Today. Trans. Stanley
Appelbaum; ed. R. C. Dale. New York: Dover, 1972.
---. Reflections
on the Cinema. London: William Kimber,
1953.
Clarke, Eric F.
Rhythm and Timing in Music. The Psychology of Music. 2nd ed., ed. Diana Deutsch. San Diego: Academic P,
1999. 473-500.
---. Ways of
Listening: An Ecological Approach to the Perception of Musical Meaning. New York: Oxford U P, 2005.
Cocteau, Jean. A
Call to Order. Trans. Rollo H. Meyers.
London: Faber and Gwyer, 1926.
---. Thtre
de poche. Monaco: Editions du Rocher, 1955.
Cohen, Annabel
J. Music Cognition and the Cognitive Psychology of Film Structure. Canadian
Psychology 43.4 (2002): 215-232.
Collins, Nick
and Fredrik Olofsson. klipp av: Live Algorithmic Splicing and Audiovisual
Event Capture. Computer Music Journal
30.2 (2006): 8-18.
Cook, Nicholas.
Analysing Musical Multimedia. New York:
Oxford U P, 1998.
Copeland,
Roger. Beyond Expressionism: Merce Cunninghams Critique of the Natural. Dance
History: An Introduction. Ed. Janet
Adshead-Lansdale and June Layson. London: Routledge, 1983. 182-197.
---. Fatal
Abstraction. Dance Theatre Journal 14.1
(1998): 38-42.
---. Merce
Cunningham: The Modernizing of Modern Dance.
New York: Routledge, 2004.
Cowell, Henry.
How Relate Music and Dance? The Dance Observer 1.5 (1934), 52-53.
Cross, Ian.
Music, Cognition, Culture, and Evolution. Annals of the New York Academy
of Sciences 930 (1999): 28-42.
Cunningham,
Merce. A Collaborative Process between Music and Dance. Tri-Quarterly 54 (1982): 173-186. Rpt. in Merce
Cunningham: Dancing in Space and Time. Ed.
Richard Kostelanetz. Chicago: Chicago Review P, 1992. 138-150.
Dissanayake,
Ellen. Art and Intimacy: How the Arts Began.
Seattle: U of Washington P, 2000.
Drake-Boyt,
Elizabeth M. Dance As a Project of the Early Modern Avant-Garde. PhD dissertation, Florida State U, 2005.
Eitan, Zohar
and Roni Y. Granot. How Music Moves: Musical Parameters and Listeners Images
of Motion. Music Perception 23.3
(2006): 221-247.
Flinn, Caryl. Strains
of Utopia: Gemder, Nostalgia, and Hollywood Film Music. Princeton: Princeton U P, 1992.
Fogelsanger,
Allen. On the Edges of Music: Trisha Browns Set and Reset and Twelve Ton Rose. Proceedings of Sound Moves: An
International Conference on Music and Dance, Roehampton University, London. 2005. 39-46.
<http://www.roehampton.ac.uk/soundmoves/SoundMovesConference2005_Proceedings.pdf>.
Friberg, Anders
and Johan Sundberg. Does Music Performance Allude to Locomotion?: A Model of
Final Ritardandi Derived from Measurements of Stopping Runners. Journal of
the Acoustical Society of America 105
(1999): 1469-84.
Gabrielsson,
Alf. Adjective Ratings and Dimension Analyses of Auditory Rhythm Patterns. Scandinavian
Journal of Psychology 14.4 (1973): 244-60.
Garafola, Lynn.
Dance, Film, and the Ballets Russes. Dance Research 16.1 (1998): 3-25.
---. Diaghilevs
Ballets Russes. New York: Oxford U P, 1989.
---.
Diaghilevs Musical Legacy. Legacies of Twentieth-Century Dance. Middletown: Wesleyan U P, 2005. 45-53.
Gibson, James
Jerome. The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum, 1979.
---. The
Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems.
Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1966.
Gourlay,
Kenneth A. The Non-Universality of Music and the Universality of Non-Music. The
World of Music 26.2 (1984): 25-37.
Hagen, Edward
H. and Gregory A. Bryant. Music and Dance as a Coalition Signaling System. Human
Nature 14 (2003): 21-51.
Hagendoorn,
Ivar. Some Speculative Hypotheses about the Nature and Perception of Dance and
Choreography. Journal of Consciousness Studies 11.3-4 (2004): 79-110.
Hanna, Judith
Lynne. Is Dance Music?: Resemblances and Relationships. World of Music 24.1 (1982): 57-69.
---. To
Dance Is Human: A Theory of Nonverbal Communication. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1979.
Hodgins, Paul. Relationships
between Score and Choreography in Twentieth-Century Dance: Music, Movement, and
Metaphor. Lewiston: E. Mellon Press, 1992.
Humphrey,
Doris. The Art of Making Dances. Ed.
Barbara Pollack. New York: Rinehart, 1959.
Iwamiya,
Shin-ichiro. Interactions between Auditory and Visual Processing when
Listening to Music in an Audio Visual Context: 1. Matching, 2. Audio Quality. Psychomusicology 13 (1994): 133-154.
Jordan,
Stephanie. Music Puts a Time Corset on the Dance. Dance Chronicle 16.3 (1993): 295-321.
Keil, Charles.
Motion and Feeling through Music. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 24 (1966): 337-349.
Kirby, Michael.
Futurist Performance. New York: E. P.
Dutton, 1971.
Kramer,
Jonathan D. The Time of Music: New Meanings, New Temporalities, New
Listening Strategies. New York: Schirmer,
1988.
Krumhansl,
Carol L. and Diana Lynn Schenck. Can Dance Reflect the Structural and
Expressive Qualities of Music? A Perceptual Experiment on Balanchines Choreography
of Mozarts Divertimento No. 15. Musicae Scientiae 1.1 (1997): 63-85.
Kylian, Jiri. Black
and White Ballets. Image Entertainment,
1995.
Leman, Marc and
Antonio Camurri. Understanding Musical Expressiveness using Interactive
Multimeda Platforms. Musicae Scientiae,
special issue on Interdisiplinary Musicology (2005/2006): 209-233.
Lipscomb, Scott
D. and Roger A. Kendall. Perceptual Judgement of the Relationship between
Musical and Visual Components in Film. Psychomusicology 13 (1994): 60-98.
Martin, John
Joseph. The Modern Dance. New York: A.
S. Barnes, 1933.
McGurk, Harry
and John MacDonald. Hearing Lips and Seeing Voices. Nature 264 (1976): 746–748.
McNeill,
William Hardy. Keeping Together in Time: Dance and Drill in Human History. Cambridge: Harvard U P, 1995.
Mellers,
Wilfrid H. Erik Satie and the Problem of Contemporary Music. Music &
Letters 23.3 (1942): 210-227.
Merker, Bjrn.
Synchronous Chorusing and Human Origins. Ch. 18 in The Origins of Music. Ed. Nils L. Wallin, Bjrn Merker and Steven Brown.
Cambridge: MIT P, 2000. 315-327.
Meyer, Leonard
B. Emotion and Meaning in Music.
Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1956.
---. Music,
The Arts, and Ideas: Patterns and Predictions in Twentieth-Century Culture,
with a New Postlude. Chicago: U of Chicago
P, 1994. Orig. pub. 1967 without the postlude.
---. A Pride
of Prejudices; or, Delight in Diversity. Ch. 7 in The Spheres of Music: A
Gathering of Essays, Chicago: U of Chicago
P, 2000a. 262-278.
---. A
Universe of Universals. Ch. 8 in The Spheres of Music: A Gathering of
Essays, Chicago: U of Chicago P, 2000b.
281-303.
Milhaud,
Darius. Le Train Bleu: Oprette danse de Jean Cocteau, Chorographie de La
Nijinska. Paris: Au Mnestrel, 1924.
Miller,
Geoffrey F. The Mating Mind: How Sexual Choice Shaped the Evolution of Human
Nature. New York: Doubleday, 2000.
Miller, Leta E.
Cages Collaborations. The Cambridge Companion to John Cage. Ed. David Nicholls. Cambridge: Cambridge U P,
2002a. 151-168.
---. Henry
Cowell and Modern Dance: The Genesis of Elastic Form. American Music 20.1 (2000b): 1-24.
Mitchell,
Robert W. & Matthew C. Gallaher. Embodying Music: Matching Music and Dance
in Memory. Music Perception 19.1
(2001): 65-85.
Neumeyer, David
with Caryl Flinn and James Buhler. Introduction. Music and Cinema. Ed. James Buhler, Caryl Flinn and David Neumeyer.
Hannover: Wesleyan U P, 2000. 1-29.
Nicholls,
David. Getting Rid of the Glue: The Music of the New York School. The New
York Schools of Music and Visual Arts: John Cage, Morton Feldman, Edgard
Varse, Willem de Kooning, Jasper Johns, Robert Rauschenberg. Ed. Steven Johnson. New York: Routledge, 2002.
17-56.
Patterson,
David. Cage and Asia: History and Sources. The Cambridge Companion to John
Cage. Ed. David Nicholls, New York:
Cambridge U P, 2002. 41-59.
Paulin, Scott
D. Richard Wagner and the Fantasy of Cinematic Unity: The Idea of the Gesamtkunstwerk in the History and Theory of Film Music. Music
and Cinema. Ed. James Buhler, Caryl Flinn
and David Neumeyer. Hannover: Wesleyan U P, 2000. 58-84.
Pudovkin,
Vsevolod Illarionovich. Asynchronism as a Principle of Sound Film. Trans.
Marie Seton and Ivor Montagu. Film Technique and Film Acting. Ed. Ivor Montagu. London: Mayflower, 1958. 183-193.
Pylyshyn, Zenon
W. and Ron W. Storm. Tracking Multiple Independent Targets: Evidence for a
Parallel Tracking Mechanism. Spatial Vision 3.3 (1988): 179-197.
Ramachandran,
Vilayanur S. and William Hirstein. The Science of Art: A Neurological Theory
of Aesthetic Experience. Journal of Consciousness Studies 6.6-7 (1999): 15-51.
Repp, Bruno H.
and Amandine Penel. Auditory Dominance in Temporal Processing: New Evidence
from Synchronization with Simultaneous Visual and Auditory Sequences. Journal
of Experimental Psychology 28.5 (2002):
1085-1099.
Ries, Frank W.
D. The Dance Theatre of Jean Cocteau.
Ann Arbor: UMI Research P, 1986.
Royce, Anya
Peterson. The Anthropology of Dance.
Bloomington: Indiana U P, 1977.
Sager, Rebecca.
Creating a Musical Space for Experiencing the Other-Self within. The
Musical Human: Rethinking John Blackings Ethnomusicology in the Twenty-First
Century. Ed. Suzel Ana Reily. Burlington:
Ashgate, 2006. 143-169.
Scholl, Brian
J. Objects and Attention: the State of the Art. Cognition 80.1-2 (2001): 1-46.
Sekuler,
Robert, Allison B. Sekuler and Renee Lau. Sound Alters Visual Motion
Perception. Nature 385 (1997): 308.
Sloboda, John
A. The Musical Mind: The Cognitive Psychology of Music. Oxford: Oxford U P, 1985.
Spackman,
Stephen. Wallingford Riegger and the Modern Dance. The Musical Quarterly 71.4 (1985): 437-467.
Spelke,
Elizabeth, William Hirst and Ulric Neisser. Skills of Divided Attention. Cognition 4 (1976): 215-230.
Watanabe,
Katsumi and Shinsuke Shimojo. Crossmodal Attention in Event Perception. Neurobiology
of Attention. Ed. Laurent Itti, Geraint
Rees and John K. Tsotsos. Amsterdam: Elsevier Academic P, 2005. 538-543.
Watkins, Glenn.
Pyramids at the Louvre: Music, Culture, and Collage from Stravinsky to the
Postmodernists. Cambridge: Harvard U P,
1994.
Yantis, Steven.
Multielement Visual Tracking: Attention and Perceptual Organization. Cognitive
Psychology 24 (1992): 295-340.
Zbikowski,
Lawrence M. Modelling the Groove: Conceptual Structure and Popular Music. Journal
of the Royal Musical Association 129.2
(2004): 272-297.
Allen
Fogelsanger is a composer and the Director of Music for the Cornell University
Dance Program. He teaches courses
that focus on the relationships between music and dance, ranging from the
theoretical through the practical, concentrating on the twentieth-century and
also on computer-interactive dance with music.
Kathleya
Afanador is a choreographer and an NSF IGERT Fellow in the Arts, Media, and
Engineering Program at Arizona State University pursuing a Ph.D. in Cognitive
Psychology. The intersection
between perception/cognition and interactive arts is her primary research area.
2006, Allen Fogelsanger and Kathleya Afanador
[1] Other explanations posit sexual selection (Miller
2000) and socialization (Dissanayake 2000).
[2] Cross (1999) offers specifically, The Igbo term nkwa [...] seems to capture the interlinking of sound and
action that characterizes music for most cultures (39). For further examples and discussion of
the myriad ways in which dance and music are categorized see Royce (1977); Hanna
(1979, 18-19); and Cross (1999, 30).
Hanna (1982, 58 and 60) includes examples of performance forms in which
the dance and music are inseparable. There have also been experiments exploring
how closely related are analogous parameters in music and dance, e.g. by
Friberg and Sundberg (1999), culminating in proposals that humans dance to
music to the extent that mirror neurons are engaged by music and result in
action (Leman & Camurri 2006).
[3] Gourlay (1984, 36) and Besson and Schn (2001, 234)
argue that music and dance are but parts of a more universal form of expression
that involves them together with all aspects of performance. A similar assertion from the
perspective of American modern dance was offered by Martin, [A]ll the arts are
linked together so closely that it is difficult to pry them apart (1933, 89).
[4] Another question is how to interpret the degree of
congruency. Cook (1998, 98-106)
develops a scheme in which any two media exist together in one of three
models: conformance (temporal congruence
as in [1] and [2] below), complementation (broader congruence as in [3] and [4]
below), or contest. The
relationship between media contributes to the meaning of multimedia; the whole
point of contest is that the broader multimedia meaning is a result of
perceived disunity of component media.
Collins and Olofsson (2006, 13) argue further that while complementation
and contest are more interesting, they depend for their effectiveness on their
contrast with conformance, a reliance on the play of expectations that recalls
Meyer (1956; 1994); they are determining effectiveness in the context of VJ
performance. On the other hand
Chion (1994, 37-39) argues that audiovisual dissonance occurs only when the meaning
of the visual element and the meaning of the auditory element are
contradictory.
[5] For movement implied by sound see Gabrielsson (1973)
and Eitan and Granot (2006).
[6] Krumhansl and Schenk also find their results to be
consistent with the conclusions of Jordan (1993).
[7] The works respectively were Solo for Prepared
Piano, part 4 of Amores (1989);
Sandstorm (1989); and Spiral Dream
(1988). Each musical selection
was interpreted [...] as a modern dance (70).
[8] In this list we roughly follow Mitchell and Gallaher
(66-67), but choose to separate pulse as a temporal aspect on its own. Merker (2000, 315), following Arom
(1991, 2000), has remarked that music seems to roughly divide into two types,
Either it is measured, that is, avails itself of a regularly paced timegiver,
or it gives up reliance on time marking altogether, and is unmeasured. Arom (2000, 27-28) notes that [i]n
Africa, nonmeasured music--music one cannot dance to--is not usually considered
music at all, but is classified as a lamentation ("tears") or a type
of signaling device.
[9] We note that there is evidence that the perception of
downbeat is culturally mediated (Cross 1999, 31). Clarke (1999, 494-496) summarizes the connection between
music, especially with a periodic rhythmic structure, and movement.
[10] Hodgins categorized choreomusical parallels as either
intrinsic or extrinsic; (1), (2), and (3) correspond to the former while (4)
corresponds to the latter.
[11] Dances without music exist both in western art dance
(Banes 1994, 312) and in folk dance (Hanna 1982, 61).
[12] Drake-Boyt (2005, 196), from which we found Buckles
quote, argues that the dance and music are remote from one another, and only
coincidentally inhabit the same time/space frame.
[13] Cited in Garafola (1989, 102-103, n. 10).
[14] Cocteaus reference to slow motion is evidence of
films impact on non-film performance.
[15] Gillmor (1988, 255) notes that Satie composed a kind
of neutral rhythmic counterpoint to the visual action. Divorced from the film the music is
practically meaningless, refusing to take on a musical identity of its own, but
as film music it fulfills its function admirably. Watkins (1994, 333) adds that Saties music-hall ensemble
[...] crossed the line from banality to boredom by mechanically projecting a
series of four- or eight-measure ostinati totally lacking in continuity, and
arbitrarily recalling musical materials without narrative consequence. Yet Clair (1972, 10) relates that Satie
timed every sequence with meticulous care, thus preparing the first musical
composition written in perfect synchronization with a film.
[16] Although primarily about a counterpoint between sound
and image, it also had applications to counterpoint between sound and
movement. The influence of film on
multimedia performance can be seen throughout the 1920s. Nijinskas Le Train Bleu (1924) included both slow motion and freeze framing
(Garafola 1998, 16), though the freeze framing occured [b]etween each ending
and the orchestra starting to play again (Cocteau in Milhaud 1924 cited by
Batson 2005). Cocteau notes the
silence of thunderous events in silent films in 1926 referring to Parade (cited in Ries 1986, 40 n. 36, from Cocteau 1926,
viii). Hindemiths Hin und
Zurck (1927) included the retrograde
of both music and visual elements (Watkins 1994, 333-334). But although the idea of simultaneity
had been present since at least the Italian Futurists, an explicit theorization
and advocation of asynchrony between sound and visual images was not produced
until the late 1920s, by Eisenstein with Pudovkin and Alexandrov, and
independently by Clair and by Balzs; see Altman (1980, 11-12) and Neumeyer,
Flinn & Buhler (2000, 15-16); also Arnheim (1957). What Pudovkin (1958, 191-193) describes
is a counterpoint of the emotional referent of the music with the images telling
the story, with the purpose of deepening the understood meaning. Clair (1953, 94-95) describes a
counterpoint of the referring sound with the image in the service of the
narrative, e.g. a car door slamming shut needs only be heard but not seen. Neumeyer et al note that Flinn (1992,
35) catches that discussents in all these texts tend to conflate imagetrack
with narrative; it is the latter, and not the imagetrack per se, that is
normally meant to parallel or to counterpoint music (16). Interest in this aspect of film seems
to wane with the arrival of talkies.
Cohen (2002) comments that Perhaps attention to speech robs processing
resources from visual structure, but this is not necessarily the case (218).
[17] The film theory and films were still operating under
the ideal of the Gesamtkunstwerk. Garafola (2005, 51-52) makes a similar
point about the Ballets Russes.
See also Paulin (2000). An
interest in arbitrary relationships in film doesnt seem to appear until
Kracauers anti-parallelism in 1960 (Paulin, 69-71).
[18] Miller (2002a, 2002b) links Cages complete
independence of music and dance to Cowells development of elastic form, which
allows internal contraction or expansion of sections in order to match the
needs of choreography. Cowell was
attempting to solve the problem that dance was a parasite on the musical form
(1934, 52). That this was indeed
seen as a problem is affirmed by Humphrey (1959, 142) and Martin (1933, 115). Spackman (1985), in his study of
composer Wallingford Rieggers involvement with modern dance (who wrote the
music for Humphreys New Dance
[1935] and With My Red Fires
[1936]), concludes that the simplicity and directness of form of Rieggers
music was reinforced by Reiggers experience with dancers, as any sort of
complex musical accompaniment would either distract attention from the dance or
simply be lost on the ear (465), thus offering more evidence of the periods
sensitivity towards the potential for interference between music and dance.
[19] Cunningham recalls that an intermediary stage was
where meter was completely abandoned (142). It should also be noted that although the dance and music in
Cunninghams later work share only a common simultaneous duration, they still
often seem to go together. This
is not surprising if, as Copeland (1983, 183) argues, the relationship of
sound, movement and decor in a Cunningham piece is not entirely
arbitrary. The most comprehensive
look at the relationship between music and dance in Cunningham and Cages work is
Copeland (2004, 145-164). For an
example of a younger choreographer, Trisha Brown, influenced by Cunningham and
Cage but determining her own varied relationships between dance and music see
Fogelsanger (2005).
[20] Banes (1983) thoroughly describes the impact of
Cunningham and Cage on the next generation of modern dance choreographers in
the Judson Dance Theater; Copeland (2004, 7-8) and Nicholls (2002, 52-53) argue
that their impact reaches far beyond dance.
[21] Patterson (2002) discusses the Asian sources of
Cages philosophy. Copland (2004,
165-182) adds more on the acceptance of simultaneity by Cunningham. Cages appreciation of simultaneity
appears to be one of enjoying the coincidences of events one sees if one
looks. This seems fundamentally
different from the Italian Futurists, who according to Kirby (1971) were
stimulated by motion pictures eliminating distance while compressing time
(47).
[22] Lipscomb and Kendall suggest that with narrative
film, music exercises a strong and consistent influence over the subject
responses to an audiovisual composite, regardless of visual stimulus (60).
Mitchell and Gallaher further note that, ambiguous visual images such
as dance may be more influenced by auditory capture than are visual images with
a strong narrative organization (67).
[23] As cited in Mitchell and Gallaher (67). A striking example from contemporary
dance is expressed by Earle Brown speaking of Springweather and People, a 1955 Merce Cunningham piece. He says, An extraordinary moment in
[the piece] was Merce coming out of the wings in a leap at a point in the music
when there was only one note being played on a violin. Merce flew on the one
held note. A dancer other than Merce—a composer other than
myself—would have supported that leap with a dramatic musical
flourishMerces leap was so stunning dramatically the way it joined that one
violin note, much more astonishing than it would have been to anything else I
could have written in order to support it (Copeland 2004, 162-163). An example within a pulsed setting
where congruence is intended is Jiri Kylians Falling Angels (1989) choreographed to Steve Reichs Drumming (1970/1971) Part I. (See Kylian [1995].)
The musics beat is divided into six pulses. Kylian alternately choreographs movement dividing the beat
into two equal parts or three equal parts, and the resulting visual stimulus
influences how easily the accompanying music may be heard as organized in
either duple or triple time.
[24] Many of Cunninghams innovations [...] serve the
ultimate goal [...] of providing us with opportunities to choose when and where
to focus our visual and auditory attention (2004, 17). See also Copeland (1998).
[25] Copeland (2004, 129-130) connects this separation of
the elements to Brechts intentional disunity.
[26] This is distinct from the syntactic and structural
listening that Meyer describes, though it certainly contributes to more fully
practicing such listening, at least when applied to, say, fugal forms. Yet polyphonic listening can increase
the understanding and appreciation of any polyphonic music, from the jazz
quartet to the Banda ongo
ensemble. See Arom (1976).
[27] Bregman (1990) argues that there are both innate and
learned processes for separating sound into separate streams of sequential aural
material (206-209), that attention can allow us to select a part of a sequence
against the dictates of the primitive process (450-453), and that we are
capable of following multiple perceptual streams (464-465). Bigand et al (2000) examine divided attention
in music listening and propose that listeners employ a strategy of integrating
multiple voices into a single, acoustically complex, stream, but this may not
apply to watching dance and listening to music. They also point out that beginning drivers have difficulty
speaking while driving, but that practice eventually makes this easier. Likewise Spelke, Hirst & Neisser
(1976) found that students could be trained to take dictation while
simultaneously reading an unrelated text.
[28] Pylyshyn and Storm (1988) showed that people can
track up to four or five moving objects simultaneously. Scholl (2001) provides a recent survey
of work in this area, and notes that results indicate that attention is split
among the target objects (10).
Additionally multiple object tracking can be enhanced by employing a
grouping strategy, for instance imagining five targets as a pentagon and
tracking the pentagon (Yantis 1992).
This is somewhat analogous to Begand et al (2000) suggesting that
musicians use learning harmony as a strategy for following multi-voiced music,
though this is a strategy for catching mistakes in the music on repetition, not
for tracking the voices the first time one hears it, which is more like what
Yantiss strategy is for.
[29] While Hagendoorns mechanism driving expectations is
our kinesthetic response to movement, Meyers (1956, 1994) is the gestalt of
pattern and good form.
Hagendoorns framework, however, does involve a second system that
invokes visual gestalt principles, as updated by Ramachandran and Hirstein
(1999), for explaining our interest in group relationships. It must be noted that while Meyers
theory of perception is grounded in a universalist Gestalt psychology, he
argues that expectations are thoroughly conditioned by experience and thus
culture (2000a, 2000b).
[30] Keils groove differs from, for example, Zbikowski
(2004), where groove is defined as a large scale, multi-layered pattern that
involves both pitch and rhythmic materials, and whose repetitions form the
basis for either a portion or all of a particular tune (275). Sager (2006, 147-148) relates Keils
groove to the bodily resonance of Blacking (1983, 57), defined as the
sensation and awareness of synchronicity with the physical movements of others
around one in a music situation (Sager, 147). This differs from more general kinesthetic response in its
specific inclusion of synchronicity (usually created by pulse) as an
integrating factor and in its reliance on the bodily motion of all
participants, not simply their sympathetic experience of virtual motion.
Keil
was writing in opposition to Meyers ideas. A second criticism of Meyers ideas is that his work uses
Western classical music, with its associated structural and syntactic listening
style, as its starting point, and empirical research has been almost uniformly
of Western listeners attending to Western music. Balkwill & Thompson (1999) provide a short list of
exceptions. In studies meant to
begin to address this, they and Balkwill, Thompson and Matsunaga (2004) found
that Western and Japanese listeners could accurately recognize basic emotions
expressed in Western and Hindustani music (the Japanese listeners in Balkwill
et al also listened to traditional Japanese music), and that these emotions
were consistently associated with common acoustic cues, such as volume, tempo,
and complexity, across cultural boundaries. These are not so much structural and syntactic as they are
psychophysical elements, of which volume and tempo, at least, may be felt as
well as heard.
[31] Sager makes a similarly proposes that music can
create a virtual space for transcendent experience (163-167).
[32] Kramer (1988) proposes a variety of types of stasis
in music, dealing largely with twentieth-century Western music in which
listeners experience of time is shaped by non-processual or minimalist
organization. Meyers (1994)
information-theoretic framework includes such possibilities; see chapters 5,
10, 11 and the Postlude.